Skip to main content

The complexity of anatomical systems

Abstract

Background

The conception of anatomical entities as a hierarchy of infinitely graduated forms and the increase in the number of observed anatomical sub-entities and structural variables has generated a growing complexity, thus highlighting new properties of organised biological matter.

Results

(1) Complexity is so pervasive in the anatomical world that it has come to be considered as a primary characteristic of anatomical systems. (2) Anatomical entities, when viewed at microscopic as well as macroscopic level of observation, show a different degree of complexity. (3) Complexity can reside in the structure of the anatomical system (having many diverse parts with varying interactions or an intricate architecture) or in its behaviour. Often complexity in structure and behaviour go together. (4) Complex systems admit many descriptions (ways of looking at the system) each of which is only partially true. Each way of looking at a complex system requires its own description, its own mode of analysis and its own breaking down of the system in different parts; (5) Almost all the anatomical entities display hierarchical forms: their component structures at different spatial scales or their process at different time scales are related to each other.

Conclusion

The need to find a new way of observing and measuring anatomical entities, and objectively quantifying their different structural changes, prompted us to investigate the non-Euclidean geometries and the theories of complexity, and to apply their concepts to human anatomy. This attempt has led us to reflect upon the complex significance of the shape of an observed anatomical entity. Its changes have been defined in relation to variations in its status: from a normal (i.e. natural) to a pathological or altered state introducing the concepts of kinematics and dynamics of anatomical forms, speed of their changes, and that of scale of their observation.

Background

Since the early 1950s, the concept of spatial conformation in general inorganic, organic and particularly biological chemistry has assumed a fundamental role in the study of the various properties of biological macromolecules (nucleic acids, proteins, carbohydrates, lipids) [1]. Because of the technologies of three-dimensional analysis, this concept is currently used in modern biology. The biological polymers that have been most widely studied in structural and functional terms are proteins and nucleic acids (DNA and RNA) [2–5].

It is now well established that the information needed to determine the three-dimensional structure of a protein is entirely contained in its linear amino acid sequence. It is likewise known that abrupt changes in environmental conditions (pH, temperature, pressure) may reversibly or irreversibly alter the tri-dimensional structure of a biological macromolecule, and thus change its specific function [6]. However, conformational change is a still widely discussed concept. The definition of the spatial conformation of either a microscopic or a macroscopic anatomical structure (sub-cellular entity, cell, tissue, organ, apparatus, organism), and the definition of a change or modification in its shape, are still unresolved problems, much debated by contemporary morphologists [7–12].

In its general sense, the term structure denotes the property resulting from the configurations of the parts that form a Whole and their reciprocal relationships to each other and to the Whole itself. On the basis of this definition, two properties of all anatomical systems made up of organised biological matter can be highlighted:

  1. a.

    every anatomical structure is capable of expressing a particular function in a particular context;

  2. b.

    the different configurations and functions of an anatomical entity emerge from structures organised in overlapping hierarchical levels.

The term 'organised biological matter' denotes anything that (1) has its own shape and dimension, i.e. space-filling property, and (2) can reproduce or replicate itself in such a way as to give rise to 'entities' that are similar in shape, dimension and functional properties to their progenitors.

It is well known that human cells differ in their shapes, dimensions and sizes. All cells making up an adult organism derive from a single progenitor cell, from which arises an enormous number of cells with different shapes, dimensions, sizes, chemical compositions and physiological characteristics in a complex and dynamic process known as cell differentiation [1, 13].

Certain cells have specific, particular and consequently invariable characteristic shapes, regardless of whether they are isolated or grouped to form more complex anatomical entities known as tissues (Figure 1). However, other cells are subject to conformational changes that depend particularly on the mechanical action exerted by their environment, the compression induced by contiguous cells, and either the complicated relationships between the cells and the extra-cellular matrix involved in the creation of tissue, or the surface tension of the biological fluid in which the cells are immersed [11, 12].

Figure 1
figure 1

Intra-cellular and/or extra-cellular stimuli determine the shape of an animal cell. In many cases intricate relationships between sub-cellular entities, such as the cytoskeleton, and environmental variables influence the cell's shape, dimension and size. Liver parenchymal cells, called hepatocytes, are roughly polyhedral in situ (a) but when they are dissociated and immersed in a culture medium gradually take on a spherical shape. Tumoral liver cells may drastically change their morphological characteristics, as result of a high number of variables that influence the global behaviour of the cell (b).

Liver parenchymal cells (hepatocytes) are roughly polyhedral in situ but, when they are dissociated and immersed in a culture medium, gradually take on a spherical shape (Figure 1) [14, 15]. It has been widely demonstrated that grouped cells respect the laws of cytomorphogenesis (morphogenetic cell development) by maximally exploiting the space available to them [7]. The variability or constancy of cell shape also depends on the physical support provided by the internal cytoskeleton [16–20].

The fact that all living organisms can be classified on the basis of their appearance is an important indication that each has a specific form (i.e. one that is retained by every example of the same species). The morphological criterion is therefore of considerable importance in identifying and taxonomically classifying living organisms.

Our aim here is to give meaning to the complex forms characterising anatomical entities in a similar way to that offered by spatial conformation in the chemical sciences. This attempt has led us to reflect upon and discuss the complex significance of the shape of an observed anatomical entity. Its changes have been defined in relation to variations in its status: from a normal (i.e. natural) to a pathological or altered state, introducing the concepts of kinematics and dynamics of anatomical forms, that of speed of their changes, and that of scale of their observation.

The complexity of living systems

Unlike an anatomical entity, and despite the fact that it has a unique shape, a crystal has no unequivocally defined size that can be used for classification; a small crystal of a given substance will always have the same general structure as a large crystal of the same type.

Any fragment of a crystal has the same physical and chemical characteristics as the whole crystal, but this is not true of any fragment of a living organism because the chemical compositions and physical properties of the individual parts do not correspond with the composition of the Whole. Furthermore, the various components of a living system are characterised by the integration of precise functional criteria that form a Whole [21].

Returning once again to crystals, their macroscopic structures can easily be predicted on the basis of their microscopic structures; they lack what are called emergent properties: i.e. those that strictly depend on the level of organisation of the material being observed (Figure 2).

Figure 2
figure 2

Human beings are complex hierarchical systems consisting of a number of hierarchical levels of anatomical organization (molecules, sub-cellular entities, cells, tissues, organs, apparatuses, and organism) that interrelate differently with each other to form networks of growing complexity.

The existence of different organisational levels governed by different laws was first indicated by systemist biologists, who stressed that a fundamental characteristic of the structural organisation of living organisms is their hierarchical nature (Figure 2). One of the pre-eminent characteristics of the entire living world is its tendency to form multi-level structures of "systems within systems", each of which forms a Whole in relation to its parts and is simultaneously part of a larger Whole.

Systemism was born in the first half of the twentieth century as a reaction to the previous mechanistic movement (also known as reductionism). It was based on an awareness that classical causal/deterministic schemata are not sufficient to explain the variety of interactions characterising living systems. Advances in the fields of cybernetics and biology led to the proposition of new interpretative models that were better suited to identifying and describing the complexity of phenomena that could no longer be seen as abstractly isolated entities divisible into parts or explicable in terms of temporal causality, but needed to be studied in terms of the dynamic interactions of their parts. The word system means "putting together". Systemic understanding literally means putting things in a context and establishing the nature of their relationships, and implies that the phenomena observed at each level of organisation (molecules, sub-cellular entities, cells, tissues, organs, apparatuses and organisms) have properties that do not apply lower or higher levels (Figure 2).

As we have already said, according to systemic thought, the essential properties of a living being belong to the Whole and not to its component parts. This led to the fundamental discovery that, contrary to the belief of René Descartes, biological systems cannot be understood by means of reduction [21–24]. The properties of the individual component parts can only be understood in the context of the wider Whole.

The biologist and epistemologist Ludwig von Bertalanffy provided the first theoretical construction of the complex organisation of living systems [25]. Like other organic biologists, he firmly believed that to understand biological phenomena, new modes of thought that went beyond the traditional methods of the physical sciences were required [26, 27]. According to Bertalanffy, living beings should be considered as complex systems with specific activities to which the principles of the thermodynamics of "closed" systems studied by physicists do not apply. Unlike closed systems (in which a state of equilibrium is established), open systems remain in a stationary state far from equilibrium and are characterised by the input and output of matter, energy and information [28].

James Grier Miller first introduced the Living System Theory (LST) about how living systems 'work', how they maintain themselves and how they develop and change [29]. By definition, living systems are open, self-organizing systems that have the peculiar characteristics of life and interact with their environment. This takes place by means of information, matter and energy exchanges. The term self-organization defines an evolutionary process where the effect of the environment is minimal, i.e. where the generation of new, complex structures takes place fundamentally in and through the system itself [30, 31]. In open systems, it is the continuous flow of matter and energy that allows the system to self-organize and to exchange entropy with the environment. Supported by a plethora of scientific data, LST asserts that all the great variety of living entities that evolution has generated are complexly structured open systems [32]. They maintain thermodynamically improbable energy states within their boundaries by continuous interactions with their environments [32–34].

LST indicates that living systems exist at eight levels of increasing complexity: cells, organs, organisms, groups, organizations, communities, societies, and supranational systems [29, 32–34]. All living systems are organized into critical subsystems, each of which is a structure that performs an essential life process. A subsystem is thus identified by the process it carries out. LST is resulted an integrated approach to studying biological and social systems, the technology associated with them, and the ecological systems of which they are all parts [35, 36].

Exploration of the phenomena of life at increasingly microscopic levels (genome) showed that the characteristics of all living systems are encoded in their chromosomes by means of a single chemical substance that has a universal transcription code [1]. In this sense, biological research became largely reductionist (i.e. increasingly involved in the analysis of molecular details). Like its seventeenth-century mechanistic predecessor, it produced an enormous amount of significant data concerning the precise structure of individual genes without knowing how these communicate and cooperate with each other in the development of an organism and its structural and functional modifications. Through continuing fundamental advances in molecular and cellular biology, molecular biologists discovered the basic building bricks of life, but this did not help them to understand the fundamental integrational processes of living beings [21–24]. As Sidney Brenner said: "In one way, you could say all the genetic and biological work of the last sixty years could be considered a long interlude....We have come full circle – back to the problems left behind unsolved. How does a damaged organism regenerate with exactly the same structure it had before? How does the egg form the organism? ....In the next twenty-five years, we are going to have to teach biologists another language....I do not know yet what its name is; nobody does... ...It is probably wrong to believe that all logic lies at molecular level. It may be that we will need to go beyond the mechanisms of a clock" [29].

In fact, a new language has emerged over the past few years that makes it possible to interpret and understand living organisms as highly integrated systems [26, 37–46]. Based on the concept of the complexity of the living, this language has given rise to several branches of study concerning the structure and organization of living organisms (such as the fractal geometry of Benoit Mandelbrot and other non-Euclidean geometries [47]) and the biological phenomena that take place within them (such as the Theory of Dynamic Systems, the Catastrophe Theory of René Thom, and the Chaos Theory [48–52]).

The kinematics and dynamics of anatomical forms

It would therefore be desirable to introduce the concept of the complexity of form into the anatomical sciences and encourage awareness that an anatomical structure observed at sub-microscopic level is governed by different laws when it is observed at microscopic or macroscopic level (Figure 3).

Figure 3
figure 3

Complex dynamical changes in humans at different level of spatial organization. A. Examples of chromosomal alterations (mutations): a) deletion of a tract of DNA; b) duplication of a tract of DNA sequence. B. The progressive changes occurring in the nucleus and cytoplasm that accompany the death of a cell. a) Normal cell; b) The nucleus becomes contracted and stains intensely. The cytoplasm is pinker, showing that it binds eosin (a common histochemical stain) more avidly. c) The nucleus disintegrates, appearing as a more or less central area of dispersed chromatin. This phase is called karyorrhexis. d) All nuclear material has now disappeared (kariolysis) and the cytoplasm stains an intense red colour. C. The final appearance of the liver (a) when it assumes the state of cirrhosis (b). Cirrhosis is the final stage of several pathogenic mechanisms operating either alone or in concert to produce a liver diffusely involved by fibrosis (abnormal extra-cellular matrix deposition) and the formation of structurally abnormal parenchymal nodules. D. Human life: from the embryonic stage of morula (a), through that of foetus (b), to the adult being (c). The times elapsing in the variousdynamical processes exemplified (A-D) are very different (simplified by green bars), ranging from nanoseconds to years. It is interesting to highlight the inverse relationship between the level of anatomical complexity and timescale.

One of the fundamental problems facing the human mind is that of the succession of forms, introduced by René Thom in his book "Stabilité Structurelle et Morphogenèse. Essai d'une théorie générale des modèles", first published in 1972 [48]. Whatever the ultimate nature of reality may be, it is undeniable that our Universe contains a variety of natural objects and living beings. These things and beings are forms: i.e. structures equipped with a certain morphological and functional stability that occupy a certain portion of space and last a certain length of time. It is a commonplace that the Universe is an incessant birth, development, and destruction of forms [48].

The succession of anatomical forms thus brings us to define:

  1. a.

    The kinematics of anatomical forms, which studies temporal transformations of an anatomical form without considering the nature of the entities to which it belongs or what causes changes (Figure 4a). When an anatomical form changes, one or more of its qualities is modified in comparison with analogous anatomical forms that are considered unchanged: e.g. a cell can change its shape or one of its associated qualities in a tissue in which other cells remain unchanged. The set of unchanged anatomical forms is called the reference system. A cell can therefore be said to be in a state of morphological stability or a phase of modification in relation to a particular reference system, depending on whether its shape remains the same or varies over time in comparison with the other cells in the system (i.e. the tissue).

Figure 4
figure 4

Kinematics and dynamics of human dendritic cells and macrophage differentiation in vitro. Cultured in vitro, monocytes may change their shape, dimension and size when opportunely stimulated by specific growth factors. Kinematics studies these changes without considering the nature of the entities to which they belong or what causes the changes (A). Cultivation in vitro with Granulocyte Macrophage-Colony Stimulating Factor (GM-CSF) alone or with Interleukin-4 (IL-4) selectively determines differentiation into macrophages or dendritic cells (B). In this case the study of the temporal transformations of primary monocytes in relation to the causes determining the changes, is defined as dynamics of the anatomical forms.

  1. b.

    The dynamics of anatomical form, which studies the temporal transformations of an anatomical form in relation to the causes of the changes. An anatomical form in a state of morphological stability tends to preserve its shape in the surrounding space. However, if we apply any (internal or external) factor u, it abandons this state of 'rest' and enters a phase of modification (Figure 4b). This factor, which can be considered a true physical force, may act on the elements determining the shape of the system (e.g. in the cell system: the plasmalemma or cytoskeleton) and/or those determining its function or its internal points (e.g. the nucleus, mitochondria, and the smooth and rough endoplasmic reticulum) [53]. The change in shape can be considered as a non-linear dynamic system that advances through states that are qualitatively different (Figure 4). The word 'state' denotes the pattern configuration of a system at a particular instant, which is specified by a large number of dynamic variables. A dynamic system can be characterised by a set of different states or possible pattern configurations (x) and a number of transitions or steps (x) from one state to another during a certain time interval (t). When the transitions are caused by a generating element (u), the temporal behaviour of the system can be described by the general equation:

    x = f (x, u, t)

    where f is a non-linear function and the dot denotes a differentiation with respect to time (t).

  2. c.

    The speed of change is the time necessary for a change in shape to occur or for the development of a perceptible difference between the modified entity and its unchanged reference system. In quantitative terms, it means the rapidity of the transformation of the anatomical form. However, the parameter time depends on a large number of variables that are interconnected in a multitude of ways and in a non-linear manner [53]. This makes it extremely difficult to predict the exact time interval between two successive states. Although conformational changes are a continuum, differentiation into successive states is commonly based on differences in shape, dimensions or functional activity (Figure 4).

    Modelling the complexity of living beings should take into account the 10–12 order-of-magnitude span of timescales for events in biological systems, whether molecular (ion channel gating: 10-6 seconds), cellular (mitosis: 102-103 seconds), or physiological (cancer progression, ageing: 108 seconds).

  3. d.

    The scale of observation, by which is meant the level at which the interrelated parts of a complex structure is being studied.

It must be emphasised that observed morphological patterns can often be conceptualised as macro-scale manifestations of micro-scale processes. However, observed patterns or system states are created or influenced by multiple processes and controls. Furthermore, those multiple processes operate at multiple spatial and temporal scales, both larger and smaller than the scale of observation.

It is also necessary to highlight that there is no one 'true' value for a measurement [52]. The measured value of any property of a biological object depends on the characteristics of the object. When these characteristics depend on the resolution of measurement, then the value measured depends on the measurement resolution. This dependence is called the scaling relationship [47]. Self-similarity specifies how the characteristics of an object depend on the resolution and hence determines how the value measured for a property depends on the resolution [47, 52].

Conclusive key points

One of the basic problems in evaluating complex living forms and their changes is how to analyse them quantitatively. Although mathematical thought has not had the same impact on biology and medicine as on physics, the mathematician George Boole pointed out that the structure of living matter is subject to numerical relationships in all of its parts, and that all its dynamic actions are measurable and connected by defined numerical relationships. Boole saw human thought in mathematical terms and, given its nature, mathematics holds a fundamental place in human knowledge.

The origins of the interest of mankind in the mathematics of form go back to ancient times, when it coincided with the manifestation of specific practical needs and, more generally, the need to describe and represent the surrounding world. The use of geometry to describe and understand reality is essential insofar as it makes it possible to reconstruct the inherent rational order of things. According to Pythagoras, real knowledge was necessarily mathematical. This idea continued until the early years of the seventeenth century, when Galileo re-proposed the observations made by Pythagoras, with no substantial modification, by affirming that the Universe is written in the language of mathematics, whose letters are triangles, circles and other geometric figures.

However, during the first half of the twentieth century, it was discovered that the geometric language of Euclid is not the only possible means of making axiomatic formulations, but that other geometries exist that are as self-consistent as classical geometry. This led to the flourishing of new geometrical languages capable of describing new spatial imaginations in rigorous terms. While successive generations of mathematicians were elaborating a large number of new non-Euclidean geometries, the beginning of the twentieth century saw the discovery of mathematical objects that seemed at first sight to be little more than curiosities devoid of practical interest (to the extent that they were even called 'pathological'). However, in the mid-1970s, the mathematician Benoit Mandelbrot gave them new dignity by defining them as "fractal objects" and introducing with them a new language called "fractal geometry".

Fractal geometry moves in a different developmental direction from the non-Euclidean geometries. Whereas the latter are based on the collocation of familiar objects in spaces other than Euclidean space, fractal geometry stresses the nature of geometric objects regardless of the ambient space. The novelty of fractal objects lies in their infinite morphological complexity, which contrasts with the harmony and simplicity of Euclidean forms but matches the variety and wealth of complex natural forms.

In conclusion, we can highlight that the following points:

  • a) Complexity is so pervasive in the anatomical world that it has come to be considered a basic characteristic of anatomical systems.

  • b) Anatomical entities, viewed at microscopic and macroscopic level of observation, show different degrees of complexity.

  • c) Complexity can reside in the structure of the system (having many diverse parts with varying interactions or an intricate architecture) or in its behaviour. Often, complexity in structure and behaviour go together.

  • d) A complex system admits many descriptions (ways of looking at the system), each of which is only partially true. Each way of looking at a complex system requires its own description, its own mode of analysis and its own breakdown of the system into different parts;

  • e) Almost all anatomical entities display hierarchical forms: their component structures at different spatial scales, or their process at different time scales, are related to each other.

Application of these concepts promises to be useful for analyzing and modelling the real significance of the shape, dimension and size of an observed anatomical system at a given scale of observation. Further, the changes of the system can be better defined in relation to variations in its status: from a normal (i.e. natural) to a pathological or altered state.

References

  1. Alberts B, Bray D, Lewis J, Raff M, Roberts K, Watson JD: Molecular Biology of the Cell. 1994, New York & London, Gerland Publishing, Inc

    Google Scholar 

  2. Travers AA, Thompson JM: An introduction to the mechanics of DNA. Philos Transact A Math Phys Eng Sci. 2004, 362: 1265-79. 10.1098/rsta.2004.1392.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  3. Fiser A, Feig M, Brooks CL, Sali A: Evolution and physics in comparative protein structure modeling. Acc Chem Res. 2002, 35: 413-21. 10.1021/ar010061h.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  4. Sali A: Comparative protein modeling by satisfaction of spatial restraints. Mol Med Today. 1995, 1: 270-7. 10.1016/S1357-4310(95)91170-7.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  5. Mariuzza RA, Phillips SE, Poljak RJ: The structural basis of antigen-antibody recognition. Annu Rev Biophys Biophys Chem. 1987, 16: 139-59. 10.1146/annurev.bb.16.060187.001035.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  6. Koshland DE: Conformational changes: How small is big enough?. Nature Med. 1998, 10: 1112-1114. 10.1038/2605.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Thompson DW: On growth and form. 1961, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press

    Google Scholar 

  8. Day SJ, Lawrence PA: Measuring dimensions: the regulation of size and shape. Development. 2000, 127: 2977-2987.

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  9. Russell B, Motlagh D, Ashley WW: Form follows function: how muscle shape is regulated by work. J Appl Physiol. 2000, 88: 1127-1132.

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  10. Lee H, Van Vactor D: Neurons take shape. Curr Biol. 2003, 13: R152-161. 10.1016/S0960-9822(03)00080-0.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  11. Schock F, Perrimon N: Molecular mechanisms of epithelial morphogenesis. Annu Rev Cell Dev Biol. 2002, 18: 463-493. 10.1146/annurev.cellbio.18.022602.131838.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  12. Goldmann WH: Mechanical aspects of cell shape regulation and signaling. Cell Biol Int. 2002, 26: 313-7. 10.1006/cbir.2002.0857.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  13. Myster DL, Duronio RJ: To differentiate or not to differentiate?. Curr Biol. 2000, 10: R302-304. 10.1016/S0960-9822(00)00435-8.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  14. Kanamura S, Kanai K, Watanabe J: Fine structure and function of hepatocytes during development. J Electron Microsc Tech. 1990, 14: 92-105. 10.1002/jemt.1060140204.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  15. Schmucker DL: Hepatocyte fine structure during maturation and senescence. J Electron Microsc Tech. 1990, 14: 106-125. 10.1002/jemt.1060140205.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  16. Feldmann G: The cytoskeleton of the hepatocyte. Structure and functions. J Hepatol. 1989, 8: 380-386.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  17. Jamora C, Fuchs E: Intercellular adhesion, signalling and the cytoskeleton. Nat Cell Biol. 2002, 4: E101-108. 10.1038/ncb0402-e101.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  18. Huntley GW, Benson DL, Colman DR: Structural remodeling of the synapse in response to physiological activity. Cell. 2002, 108: 1-4. 10.1016/S0092-8674(01)00631-6.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  19. Scott EK, Luo L: How do dendrites take their shape?. Nat Neurosci. 2001, 4: 359-365. 10.1038/86006.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  20. Knust E: Control of epithelial cell shape and polarity. Curr Opin Genet Dev. 2000, 10: 471-475. 10.1016/S0959-437X(00)00115-5.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  21. Powell K: All systems go. J Cell Biol. 2004, 165: 299-303. 10.1083/jcb.200404013.

    Article  PubMed Central  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  22. Nurse P: Reductionism. The ends of understanding. Nature. 1997, 387: 657-10.1038/42600.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  23. Nurse P: Reductionism and explanation in cell biology. Novartis Found Symp. 1998, 213: 93-101.

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  24. Rose S: What is wrong with reductionist explanations of behaviour?. Novartis Found Symp. 1998, 213: 176-86.

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  25. Bertalanffy LV: General system theory. 1968, New York, Braziler

    Google Scholar 

  26. Chang L, Ray LB: Whole-istic biology. Science. 2002, 295: 1661-10.1126/science.295.5560.1661.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Kitano H: Computational systems biology. Science. 2002, 295: 1662-1664. 10.1126/science.1069492.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  28. Bertalanffy LV: The theory of open systems in physics and biology. Science. 1950, 111: 23-29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. Miller GJ: Living systems. 1978, New York, McGraw-Hill

    Google Scholar 

  30. Kauffman AS: The origins of order: Self-Organization and Selection in Evolution. 1993, New York, Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  31. Haken H: Information and Self-Organization: A Macroscopic Approach to Complex Systems. 2000, Berlin, Springer

    Google Scholar 

  32. Miller GJ, Miller LJ: Introduction: the nature of living systems. Behav Sci. 1990, 35: 157-163.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  33. Miller GJ: Living systems: basic concepts. Behav Sci. 1965, 10: 193-237.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  34. Miller GJ: Living systems: structures and processes. Behav Sci. 1965, 10: 337-379.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  35. Braham MA: A general theory of organization. Gen Systems. 1973, 18: 13-24.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Laszlo E: The Systems View of the World: A Holistic Vision for Our Time. 1996, Cresskill, NJ, Hampton Press

    Google Scholar 

  37. Brenner S: The limits of Reductionism in Biology. Edited by: G Bock, JA Goode. 1998, Novartis Found Symp 213, London, John Wiley, 106-116.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Szathmary E, Jordan F, Pal C: Molecular biology and evolution. Can genes explain biological complexity?. Science. 2001, 292: 1315-1316. 10.1126/science.1060852.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  39. No Authors listed: End of the interlude?. Nat Biotechnol. 2004, 22: 1191-10.1038/nbt1004-1191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  40. Stephanopoulos G, Alper H, Moxley J: Exploiting biological complexity for strain improvement through systems biology. Nat Biotechnol. 2004, 22: 1261-1267. 10.1038/nbt1016.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  41. Goldenfeld N, Kadanoff LP: Simple lessons from complexity. Science. 1999, 284: 87-89. 10.1126/science.284.5411.87.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  42. Noble D: Modeling the heart – from genes to cells to the whole organ. Science. 2002, 295: 1678-1682. 10.1126/science.1069881.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  43. Service RF: Complex systems. Exploring the systems of life. Science. 1999, 284: 80-1, 83. 10.1126/science.284.5411.80a.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  44. Weng G, Bhalla US, Iyengar R: Complexity in biological signaling systems. Science. 1999, 284: 92-96. 10.1126/science.284.5411.92.

    Article  PubMed Central  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  45. Koch C, Laurent G: Complexity and the nervous system. Science. 1999, 284: 96-98. 10.1126/science.284.5411.96.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  46. Butcher EC, Berg EL, Kunkel EJ: Systems biology in drug discovery. Nat Biotechnol. 2004, 22: 1253-1259. 10.1038/nbt1017.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  47. Mandelbrot B: The fractal geometry of nature. 1983, New York, Freeman

    Google Scholar 

  48. Thom R: Stabilité Structurelle et Morphogènes. Essai d'une théorie générale des modèles. 1972, Paris, InterEditions

    Google Scholar 

  49. Abraham R: Complex dynamics. 1991, Santa Cruz, Aerial Press

    Google Scholar 

  50. Abraham R, Shaw C: Dynamics, The geometry of behavior. 1992, Reading MA, Addison-Wesley

    Google Scholar 

  51. Gleick J: Chaos: Making a New Science. 1987, New York, Penguin Books

    Google Scholar 

  52. Bassingthwaighte JB, Liebovitch LS, West BJ: Fractal physiology. 1994, New York, Oxford University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  53. Grizzi F, Franceschini B, Chiriva-Internati M, Hermonat PL, Shah G, Muzzio PC, Dioguardi N: The complexity and the microscopy in the anatomical sciences. Science, Technology and Education of Microscopy: an Overview. Spain, Formatex. 2003

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Fabio Grizzi.

Authors’ original submitted files for images

Rights and permissions

Open Access This article is published under license to BioMed Central Ltd. This is an Open Access article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License ( https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/2.0 ), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Grizzi, F., Chiriva-Internati, M. The complexity of anatomical systems. Theor Biol Med Model 2, 26 (2005). https://doi.org/10.1186/1742-4682-2-26

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1186/1742-4682-2-26

Keywords